Economists and Climate Change – Homework Comes First
Updated on 05 April 2024
A Comment to Henderson
Aldo Matteucci – DiploFoundation, Geneva (Switzerland)
David HENDERSON (World Economics X, 1) is certainly right in highlighting the “uncritical and over-presumptive ways in which [economists] have dealt with the scientific aspects” of climate change. All of his points are well taken and deserve expeditious and thorough treatment. As the aging IBM-adage says: garbage in – garbage out. I may add for good measure Oskar MORGENSTERN’s forgotten lesson about the inevitable loss of information when data are numerically-mathematically processed [i]. Models may inherently (and inadvertedly) produce garbage as they grind good numbers. There are inherent limits to improving the data, however. Even were HENDERSON’s points implemented by tomorrow at dusk – the science would continue to provide surprises and discoveries as of the day after. Climate study is truly ‘work in progress’: and there is no end in sight, just asymptotic accumulation of knowledge. We’ll never know for sure what lies ahead: complex systems like the climate are structurally unpredictable, and talk about impending ‘tipping points’ is so much speculation – as the millions of butterflies attest, whose flapping of the wings did not create a hurricane in New York. As crucial as the demand for better data is – it is only half the task. Lord KEYNES’ gently chided all of us: “Practical men, who believe themselves to be quite exempt from any intellectual influence, are usually the slaves of some defunct economist.” The current predicament of the economic profession after the collapse of the ‘rational expectations’ paradigm should alert us to the danger of using simplifying assumptions, axioms and incomplete models in policy making. We may upgrade the facts; but do we verify and upgrade the underlying thinking? Or might not the opposite be true: hopeful paradigms, tentative insights, conjectures or working hypotheses are ‘stretched’ until they become platitudes or harden into dogma? This comment, therefore, aims to enlarge the discussion. When HENDERSON speaks of received opinion he is right – albeit incomplete. ‘Received opinion’ refers not just to the underlying science: it refers even more to the conceptual framework currently being used to address the issue. The following might then be seen as a preliminary and provisional list of conceptual and methodological issues that economists could usefully converse about while sitting around the campfire of reason waiting for the lumbering science train to catch up. A review of our conceptual models may have consequences beyond the better treatment of better data. It may, hopefully, help change the kind of data we use by highlighting gaps and stimulating science to look beyond its own – quite limited – conceptual framework. For all its strengths the IPCC process does not undertake or commission research, neither on its own account, nor on behest of ‘policy’. Is it not strange that ‘policy’ has no requests of its own to make to science? After all, economists, not the statistical bodies, have driven the definition and collection of economic data. Is it not somewhat anomalous that there is no institutionalised dialogue on data between ‘policy’ and ‘science’? 1. Naming the issue Mankind tells stories to itself – that’s the way we all make sense of chaotic reality. Depending on the choice of point of view – assumptions rather than findings – or which interests are foremost on the story-teller’s mind, stories may vary fundamentally[ii]. These stories vie for broader acceptance and thus social legitimacy. Whoever controls ‘the story’ also controls the framework of a negotiation and – to a good extent – the outcome. ‘Soft power’ is much about controlling the ‘story’. Tackling an issue thus begins with its proper ‘naming’. ‘Naming’ and the choice of an analytical framework for policy action are closely related. For historical reasons ‘climate change’ has been ‘named’ an ‘environmental’ and ‘pollution’ problem, which is certainly not wrong as to its origins. This kind of naming has consequences for the way the issue is tackled, however: (a) it implicitly favours mitigation and abatement policies by analogy with other pollution problems; (b) it focuses on the damage, while underplaying possible benefits of climate change; (c) it introduces an implicit element of ‘guilt’ (as enshrined in the ‘polluter pays’ principle<a href="[iii]), rather than pointing towards a common responsibility, or the most economic solution to the problem; (d) It tends to focus on ‘material balances’, while underplaying the role of social institutions and inventiveness (technology) in adapting to the impact. Not only does it hide complementarities/ competitivenesses in policies, but it might misdirect efforts away from needed social reforms. This perception of the problem, coupled with projections of irreversible environmental degradation, has led to what I might call ‘environment/climate change exceptionalism’ – the contention that the problem is so imminent and immense as to push aside all other concerns, or make them subsidiary to the solution of the core issue. On the contrary, I’d opine that climate change policies are not a ‘separate’ issue but one of the legs of the tripod: resources, technologies, and environment (of which climate change is part), which are the long term basis of sustainable development. To state it bluntly: climate change policies are part of social and economic development policies – and we should name them correspondingly. While climate change policies are a necessary component of development, they are not sufficient, not even to save us from the impending doomsday. Three reasons in particular may be advanced: (1) Most of the ‘impacts’ of climate change (from its impacts on health to food security) concern what we define currently as ‘social and economic development’. We are confronted with the choice whether to address the issues directly (e.g. through health policies or poverty reduction) or indirectly by addressing climate change issues[iv]; (2) Climate change is intimately connected with energy policy (some say it is 80 % so) – and energy is what drives economic development. To argue for decarbonification is to argue for a major change in energy and development policies; (3) Public policies all demand resources – be they from the public purse, private firms, households, or individuals. While we all might ‘do more’, in the end it is a matter of priorities, and doing A means that C and D will not receive as much attention. One may argue then, with A. K. SEN, that “enhancement of human freedom is the main objective and the primary means of development.”[v]. This applies to climate change policy no less than any other social and development policy. There is no basis or justification for ‘climate change exceptionalism’. Sustainable development cannot be divorced from social justice. A solution that would have assets trickle up and some income trickle down would prove unworkable even before the ‘ecological limits’ were reached. Climate change policies that would advocate compression and convergence from the current worldwide or regional distribution of income would be unlikely to find approval with those large parts of humanity that have been short-changed in their development so far. The core issue facing mankind today are how to square sustainable development with resource use and environmental protection. These issues are totally intertwined. To break them out and privilege one of the tree legs is to distort our predicament. 2. The ‘precautionary principle’ – can it bear so much weight? Climate change discourse is greatly shaped by the ‘precautionary principle’. We are treated to a weekly parade of observations which, when projected into the future, portents doom: disease, famines, the image of New York’s statue of Liberty sinking under the sea – whatever. Having weighed in with such bad tidings, preventive action – de-carbonification – is presented as self-evident precaution. This scenario brooks no discussion: the case for ‘climate change exceptionalism’ rests on “better safe than sorry”. Caution, certainly a wise stance, has moved here beyond an argument from experience and hardened into principle, or even become deontological imperative – it has become a major ‘killer argument’. In some countries it has become legally binding and subject to judicial review. There are even attempts to enshrine it in international law. The inverted commas around ‘principle’ are meant to flag a logical difficulty worthy of a closer look. I’ve difficulties with a principle indiscriminately applied to justifying both mitigation and avoidance of nuclear power. This difficulty, incidentally, is far from new: Thomas Paine and David Hume at the core argued about the application of the ‘precautionary principle’ to the American and French Revolution. In hindsight, while we may usefully argue as to whether revolution is the best way to achieve liberty, we would not reject liberty out of fear that it might lead to licence. The precautionary principle is deeply conservative. By definition any change involves at least some regrets: if avoiding regrets is established as our foremost guiding light, then any change should be rejected on the grounds that we are already living in Panglossian perfection. For there will always be “known unknowns and unknown unknowns” – in the elegant formulation of a former US Secretary of Defence. Privileging ‘unknowns’ over ‘knowns’, however, debases rational discourse, while opening the field to subjective and selective bias towards catastrophism. Let’s be honest – we are more likely to believe a headline that ‘the end of the world is near’ than the prediction that ‘paradise is just around the corner’. While I may use the precautionary principle to stop my child from attempting to walk on water, I would not accept it as his excuse not to get out of bed in the morning. David RUNCIMAN[vi] and Cass R. SUNSTEIN[vii] have forcefully argued for a rational application of the ‘precautionary principle’, i.e. to replace dogma with verification of the principle in the specific context. How much of the vaulted ‘principle’ will remain, will be interesting to watch. After all, it’s this principle that got Buridan’s ass into terminal trouble. There is nothing wrong about the ‘precautionary principle’ that a good dose of common sense won’t cure. What might help, I’d argue, is to stop turning ‘an arguable argument into an obsessional fantasy’ for action. 3. The conundrum of intergenerational responsibility Unlike people, societies don’t have a finite time horizon. Despite this basic difference, we intuitively apply to policy an analogy from our individual experience and demand that ‘every generation should make reasonable allowance for the needs of the future’. As self-evident as it sounds – this principle creates significant logical problems. We all save ‘for a rainy day’. Yet a rainy day might hide another, so when should we use money we have stashed away to cover such a contingency? Mostly we die before we are able to resolve this conundrum, and either the heirs or the insurance company gets rich. This conundrum is exacerbated with public policy. There always is a ‘future generation’ to provide for. This would make ‘no use’ the only legitimate one – an obvious abdication of responsibility. We should not bequeath future generations a badly diminished world, it is said[viii]. But this view is flawed: as we transform the world we leave to future generations enormous tangible and intangible assets, albeit of a different kind. True, we may be ‘mining the environment’ – thanks to our efforts, meanwhile, human knowledge doubles every five years. Is this not compensation enough? Other ethical issues emerge. Future generations cannot tell us about their wants and preferences. At best, we can apply to them the Golden Rule (“don’t impose on others what you’d not like being imposed on you”), but that implies that values remain unchanged, or that we act in paternalistic ways, as Paul SAMUELSON opined (he rejected the Golden Rule with the caveat: “they may have other tastes…”). Conversely, future generations are in no position to compensate us for the benefits they receive from us in terms of development – they’ll inherit it all for free, warts and all. If we assume a reasonable rate of growth, future generations are likely to be much better off than we are today – at 1.5% annual growth it is over four times in 100 years. The question is then: to what extent should this generation sacrifice for the future where everyone will be richer (comparatively speaking) thanks to our inheritance? This issue is further complicated by the fact that we should atone for ‘past sins’ – the accumulation of GHG that accrued ever since industrialisation (or even civilisation?) began. Is it reasonable to expect today’s world to bear on its weak shoulders the burdens of past, present, and future? Distributional justice makes the issue even thornier. We do find it difficult to arbitrate between accumulation and distribution, and many argue that ‘trickle down’ is the best our society can achieve. Meanwhile, even should the tide raise all boats, the gap between rich and poor is getting wider – and this is perceived as unfair[ix]. Favouring future generations inevitably short-changes today’s poor. This is not just an ethical issue: it is one of political stability of our societies – rich and poor, present and future ones. 4. Toward more objective benefit-cost models What is intuitively simpler than weighing benefits and costs? Much of the climate change discourse is about benefits and costs. Ever since benefit-cost analysis emerged as a policy tool over fifty years ago, what looked as a simple counting procedure has proven to be a logical minefield. I shall list a few areas of concern, without claiming completeness. (1) Bias in identifying costs and benefits. Nothing is easier than being selective in identifying benefits and costs. The larger and more complex the issue, the greater the opportunities for identifying/ignoring costs or benefits to suit one’s prejudices. When we were young and interventionists the benefits from public action easily had the upper hand – even if meant double-counting or ignoring externalities. Now that we are old and full of regrets the pendulum has swung the other way and catastrophism seems de rigeur. Here a few examples from the current climate change discourse:- Deaths from excess heat[x] are totalled up, but ‘lives saved’ when milder winters reduce mortality from cold are ignored. Of course, they are not easily ascertained, but the inherent incompleteness of the analysis should be acknowledged and weighted.
- Desertification in the subtropics is highlighted, while the fact that wide areas in the sub-arctic regions of Canada and Russia may become available for agriculture tends to be ignored.
- False attribution of damage: increasing damage from hurricanes is e.g. shown in harrowing time series and linked to climate change. The latest IPCC Report is very cautious in linking hurricane patterns and climate change[xi]. What is obvious is that, in the last fifty years, we have been foolish enough to build in the path of hurricanes or delinquent in the upkeep of abatement measures[xii]. Should we blame climate change for our own mistakes? Are we not engaged in a convenient exercise of ‘post hoc, proper hoc’?
- Epidemics: will climate change spread malaria? This prediction is repeated quite often. Malaria was once endemic in Europe, when it was colder than today. Meanwhile malaria has been eradicated in the course of economic development and is unlikely to return even with higher mean temperatures. There is no reason to believe that this process will not continue.
- Famines: As A. SEN has shown, famines are not so much a matter of physical shortages as of lack of entitlements. In rich countries crop shortfalls are routinely compensated for with imports. True, climate change may regionally lead to crop failures – the best insurance against such famines, however, is not mitigation, but economic development with consequent enhanced entitlements. Even global shortfalls can be met adaptively, by storage, or changing food patterns.
- Epidemics: malaria might be eradicated with a targeted programme that costs say, 40 billion US$[xiii]. If climate change were to increase the total incidence of malaria by say 10%, the benefits from mitigation would be no more than the 4 billion saved from not having to treat additional instances of malaria.
- Flooding of islands: the value of mitigation in such instances might be no more than the costs of relocating the population, or the building of protective dams (e.g. in Venice).
______________
[i] Oskar MORGENSTERN (1955): On the accuracy of economic observations. 2nd. Edition. Princeton University Press, New Haven; 322 pp. [ii] A current example concerns opposite ‘stories’ vying to describe the conflict between Western and Islamic worlds. See Clifford GEERTZ (2003) Which way to Mecca? Parts I and II, New York Review of Books, June 12,/July 4. [iii] In his seminal paper: The problem of social cost, Ronald H. COASE points out that efficiency is obtained as soon as the market recognizes the effect. It is a matter of distributional justice who pays whom. See: Ronald H. COASE (1990): The firm the market and the law. Chicago University Press, Chicago, 217 pp. [iv] A good example of distortions in the current discussion of the issues may be gleaned from the fact that ‘famine’ is now being classified under ‘environment’. See: Lester R. BROWN (2009): Could food shortages bring down civilisation? Scientific American, May. It is noteworthy, incidentally, that the article, while mentioning biofuels, fails to consider change in dietary habits as a strategy for famine prevention/reduction. If poverty reduction is the best protection against regional famines one may add that global grain scarcity should lead to destocking of domestic animals first, not famine – if the income distribution is right. [v] A. K. SEN (1999): Development as Freedom. Anchor Books, New York, N.Y.; xvi + 366 pp. Pg. 53 [vi] David RUNCIMAN (2004): The Precautionary Principle. London Review of Books, 1 April. See also: Jeremy WALDRON (288): Reality check. London Review of Books, 10 April. [vii] Cass R. SUNSTEIN (2005): Laws of fear. Beyond the precautionary principle. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, xii + 234 pp. In particular, he argues for three steps: a narrow Anti-Catastrophe Principle, designed for the most serious risks; close attention to costs
Leave a Reply
Want to join the discussion?Feel free to contribute!